Are You a Garbled Environmentalist?
Meet Jason. Jason is a thoroughly modern, well-educated young man. He dabbled with agnosticism at school but is now a confirmed atheist and will only (reluctantly) enter a church for weddings and funerals. He cares about the environment, especially biodiversity, and sometimes lies awake at night worrying about the ever-expanding Red List of Threatened Species. He is involved with a local volunteer group that tackles invasive species, and he strives to save indigenous species, planting only endemic trees in his well-kept town garden. Living in New Zealand he is proud of his clean, green country, and, like any decent person, he welcomes new immigrants. Jason is so convinced of the moral rectitude of his position that he believes he could hold his own in any argument. Is he correct?
An
important part of Jason’s atheism is his belief in Darwinian evolution. Science,
he maintains, has shown beyond any doubt that the universe started with the Big
Bang, and that it has rolled out ever since without a guiding deity’s intervention.
Modern genetics has revealed the mechanism of Darwinism, whereby meiosis creates
individuals that differ in their ability to survive and reproduce in a
particular environment, and they pass this ability on to their offspring. Here
lies, in Darwin’s words, the origin of species.
Now
the mechanism of speciation is, according to Jason’s beliefs, a purely random,
physical process, generating genotypes with different phenotypes. A bit like
the output of a random-number-generating machine. So, one might ask, what’s so
special about a species? Because special they are. For example, a headline in
the Otago Daily Times of 5 March 2022 heralded the discovery of a new
plant species in the Livingstone
Mountains of Southland, New Zealand, provisionally called Chaerophyllum sp.
‘‘Livingstone’’. (Jason was very excited when he read this.) As the article
says, “The newly discovered plant will need additional research to compare it
to its close relatives before being formally considered a new species. This
research could take some time, but if it turns out the population is a new
species, then its threat status would need to be determined [emphasis added].”
Once
its threat status is determined, various conservation strategies will be put in
place. These use taxpayer’s money, involve significant effort, and can affect
the ability of people to utilise an area, or farm their land, or construct
dwellings. It’s a big deal. Yet Chaerophyllum sp. ‘‘Livingstone’’ is
indistinguishable from its closest relative without the expertise of a
taxonomist and/or cytological analysis. In a Darwinian, materialistic universe
there is no justification whatsoever for the value placed on this new,
ever-so-slightly different species, this new, reproducible set of genes. It’s
like saying 728439441 is valuable because it’s different from 728439440.
In
fact, the only possible justification for attributing such intrinsic value would
be a belief in Creationism. God created every species (all creatures great and
small), and they are valuable in as much as they are the individual products of
His divine work. It follows that Jason’s worry about threatened species is
either completely illogical or commits him to belief in a creative deity.
Ruffled
but undefeated, Jason points out the significance of what are known as ecosystem
services. These are “the many and varied benefits to humans provided by the natural
environment and from healthy ecosystems”. This is where species get their value,
he says: they provide valuable services. For the Creationist this argument is a
godsend, coming almost straight out of Genesis (1:29): “I give you all plants
that bear seed everywhere on earth, and every tree bearing fruit which yields
seed: they shall be yours for food.” Ecosystem services can be seen as just a
fancy way of saying that God has provided for us. In any case, the fact that
some organisms are beneficial to us – provide ecosystem services – doesn’t
begin to justify the significance placed on the vast majority of species on
Earth, such as Chaerophyllum sp. ‘‘Livingstone’’, which, nestling on scree
slopes high in the Alps, provides no benefit at all. Finally, it’s a bit of an
icky argument, environmentally speaking, to argue that organisms only have
value if they are valuable to humans, like domestic animals. Is that really
what you want to say, Jason, good environmentalist that you are?
Slightly
more rattled, and remembering Gaia, Jason takes up this new point and stresses
the importance of biodiversity, the biological variety of life on Earth. This
is important because it is the very range of different organisms in an
ecosystem that keep it functioning – from insects pollinating flowers to worms
structuring topsoil and invertebrates breaking down leaf litter. Biodiversity
keeps an ecosystem in balance through the way all of its constituent organisms
interact. So it’s not just ecosystem services directly benefiting humans that
are important: it’s also the overall functioning of ecosystems. This indirectly
affects our ability to live on Earth, but also keeps Gaia functioning, even if
all humans die and have no need for ecosystem services.
There
are two problems here. First, it implies that all, or perhaps most, species are
necessary to maintain adequate biodiversity on Earth. But consider the Permian–Triassic extinction event, which occurred about 252 million years ago: it killed off between
90 and 96% of all species on Earth. Of course this, the largest extinction event
ever, had huge consequences, but it does suggest, as indeed the Gaia hypothesis
proposes, that Earth is adaptable and resilient to change, and that
biodiversity can quite effortlessly cope with losing a large number of species.
The
second problem relates to Jason’s reverence for indigeneity, and especially endemicity.
(Endemic organisms occur naturally only in a single geographical location,
whereas indigenous organisms occur naturally in a geographical location but may
also occur elsewhere.) If we are purely concerned with biodiversity maintaining
ecosystem functioning, then whatever does the job gets the job. Invasive (what
in gentler times were called exotic) organisms may perform biodiversity
functions as well as or better than the locals to keep the ecosystem in
balance. In New Zealand much has been
made of the fact that birds evolved in the absence of natural predators, making
them particular susceptible to rats, stoats and feral cats, to name a few
baddies. This means endemic birds tend towards extinction without massively
expensive, labour-intensive measures, such as rodent-proof sanctuaries, in
order to survive. But if the local species aren’t tough enough to survive, why not let the tough guys like sparrows, starlings and blackbirds take over
and maintain biodiversity? Survival of the fittest. It’s how evolution works,
remember Jason?
But,
the now increasingly desperate Jason argues, creatures that belong in a place
ought to take some sort of precedence. That is where they belong. Kiwis are at
home in New Zealand, koalas are at home in Australia. They are adapted to
living there, and they have a right to live unmolested by invasive species who
come in and occupy their ecological niches and make it impossible for them to
thrive. Our native species are attacked and killed. They need to be protected against
aggressive, exotic outsiders, which should be stopped at the border, or, if
they are here already, trapped, poisoned and exterminated. Let stoats stay in
the countries where they are endemic. They don’t belong here.
That’s
an interesting argument, Jason, from the point of view of moral reasoning.
Because it follows that you believe we should keep out human invasives
(immigrants) because they don’t belong here, because they occupy our ecological
niches (take our jobs) and make it impossible for us to thrive (are a drain on
the social welfare system). In many countries native species (citizens) are
attacked and killed (Islamic terror attacks). Such immigrants need to be
stopped at the border, or, if they are already living here, trapped, poisoned
and exterminated, much like the Final Solution devised for unwanted residents
of the Greater Germanic Reich.
I
trust it’s very clear that this is a reductio ad absurdum argument. I want to
show that rationally arguing the viewpoint of a nice, decent, environmentally
sensitive atheist leads to a belief in Creationism, a disregard for endangered
species, and an advocacy of hard borders for immigration and persecution of
migrants. Just the sort of horrendous beliefs Jason despises in people who
spread “disinformation” on the internet. If Jason had said he likes and values the
native species in his environment and feels a strong desire to protect them, say,
then that would be the end of it. De gustibus non est disputandum. But he was
convinced he could argue the merits of his moral position.
David
Wolcott
Comments
Post a Comment